RELATED ARTICLES

In private, there were spiritual doubts. Now I will ask you, look at the portraits. Ask what they can tell us. He was so much drawn and painted, as if every amateur artist reached for his pencil, in wonder at what he knew to be a transitory phenomenon. History, enraged at the review of the insatiable crimes of Robespierre, has already bestowed on him a fanciful physiognomy, which she has composed of features which rather correspond with the ferocity of his soul, rather than with his real countenance. From the appearance of this bust, which is an authentic resemblance of him, his face must have been rather handsome.

His features were small, and his countenance must have strongly expressed animation, penetration and subtlety. Two years into the Revolution, she has painted a boy with a face of conspicuous sweetness, gentle and shy: In the posed portraits, he is always smiling: Then there is a sketch taken from life, , in the National Convention.

He is not smiling. He has pushed his spectacles into his hair. His eyes have moved sideways, in suspicion or a kind of dread. A man, as Belloc put it, for colour rather than ornament. The face is still very young; the expression is closed, guarded, as if he had seen something move in the shadows. By Thermidor, it appears he has aged ten years.

Similar books and articles

The final sketch, taken again from life, shows features pared to bone, jaw muscles rigid, every line drawn taut and fine. A day or two after it, Mme Tussaud took his death mask. The Revolution represented a ruinous physical struggle for its front-line personnel.


  • Templar Treasures (The Knights Templar Series Book 4).
  • Suspect citizens : women, virtue, and vice in backlash politics in SearchWorks catalog;
  • Hilary Mantel reviews ‘Robespierre’ edited by Colin Haydon and William Doyle · LRB 30 March .
  • The Faith of Phebe.
  • In the Name of the Father.

In the weeks before it, he had preserved a silence which worked on the nerves of his colleagues. His face became unreadable. But the narrative behind it is always old and always new. Danton thought he had the story straight: Imagination creates a false opposition between the two men; for most of the Revolution, there was little difference of policy between them, and Robespierre — on the principle that it is better to win even the battles you have not chosen to fight — abandoned Danton when he could do nothing more for him. But as Norman Hampson says elsewhere, the Danton of legend is hard to resist, especially since he imposed himself on contemporaries as well as posterity.

Citations per year

After his death this well-read, greedy, secretive lawyer became a sort of roaring boy, a great-hearted, common-touch, chicken-in-every-pot man. As the 19th century progressed, Robespierre acquired a set of nervous twitches and shudders, and a hideous yellow complexion highlighted by green veins. The 18th-century inch being a variable measure, he shrunk physically, while Danton expanded. Of course, most people who have written about Robespierre are men, and wish themselves to be, au fond , masculine, beneath their academic gowns or tweed jackets.

They like to believe that if it came to it they could knock their opponents down: Two essays in this collection concentrate on Robespierre in drama and in French fiction. Astonishing in form rather than content, it embellishes the legend of the world-weary philosopher done to death by a Robespierre-machine. Henry Irving played Robespierre in a Sardou melodrama of , in which the Great Terrorist was forced to compromise his principles to save his long-lost illegitimate son.

An play by Combet has a memorable stage direction. At his entry, the heavenly choir bursts into song. She was the maddest of all female Robespierrists and in this matter I yield to few.

Suspect Citizens - Women, Virtue, and Vice in Backlash Politics (Hardcover, New)

If you try to write either drama or novels about the Revolution, you have to consider your likely audience and the state of their prejudices. For historians, creative writers provide a kind of pornography. They break the rules and admit the thing that is imagined, but is not licensed to be imagined. We are likely to succumb to them, until history is written by machines; there are not two kinds of history, one sceptical and rational, and the other imaginative and erratic.

A real heroine of the Revolution is the housemaid who lit the fire with his first draft. Schama uses his narrative skill and his wealth of illustration to confirm people in the belief they already hold, which is that the Revolution was a bloody and nonsensical waste of time. For the French, of course, Schama is irrelevant, because he is telling them nothing they have not heard from their own revisionist historians.

But the scope of his enquiry is not wide. Imagination must be free, the dead have no remedy in law; all they can do is haunt you. Which, in effect, is what Robespierre does. He takes a grip on the imagination and does not easily let you go. Michelet, ambivalent about the Incorruptible, always crossing and recrossing the line of his own argument, accused Louis Blanc, Hamel and others of a corrupting partiality: In his last weeks, Robespierre stayed out of the public eye. No one supposed he was a spent force, but after the death of the Dantonists he had seemed to lose his sureness of touch.

He could not survive if he trusted nobody, and could not work out who to trust. The truth about the motives of his fellow-revolutionaries seemed to be beyond mortal reach. He had always warned that the devil had the best tunes. All that is left for him is the word which is guaranteed because it is spoken by a dying man. The Revolution, as a creative enterprise, died with him. There is a formulation in which his death is a kind of blessed release for the nation; but after it, the Terror continued, and what lay ahead was a new tyranny and 20 years of war.

In his last speech to the Convention, he said: Michelet alone at the whitewood table, Stanislawa obsessively rewinding her typewriter ribbon. On the final document his signature is unfinished. He had written just two letters of his name, before a pistol shot shattered his jaw; whether he fired the shot himself, no one really knows. Lying in his own blood in an anteroom of the Committee of Public Safety, he gestured that he wished to write, but no one would give him a pen.

I would have given him a pen, Barras said later, uneasy at the cruelty and the lack of a possible disclosure. He was half-dead when he was taken to the scaffold, and his decapitated remains were buried near the Parc Monceau. Maurice Duplay was imprisoned and driven out of business. His wife was found dead in her cell. Fear sealed the lips of witnesses, papers were burned, memories were reformulated. After the revolution of , a group of admirers tried to locate the body.

But though they dug and dug, no one was there. It looms like Death at the beginning and end of the film, and appears intermittently during it. He uses it to evoke the cold, calculating, rational nature of the state itself vertu , justice, integrity, whatever you want to call it. It was the frightfulest thing ever born of Time?

Temple University Press

One of the frightfulest. This Convention, now grown Anti-Jacobin, did, with an eye to justify and fortify itself, publish Lists of what the Reign of Terror had perpetrated: Lists of Persons Guillotined. They contain the names of, How many persons thinks the Reader? There were above Four-thousand, cries Montgaillard: It is a horrible sum of human lives, M. It is not far from the two hundredth part of what perished in the entire Seven-Years War. Such things were; such things are; and they go on in silence peaceably: History, looking back over this France through long times … confesses mournfully that there is no period to be met with, in which the general Twenty-five Millions of France suffered less than in this period which they name Reign of Terror!

But it was not the Dumb Millions that suffered here; it was the Speaking Thousands, and Hundreds, and Units; who shrieked and published, and made the world ring with their wail … that is the grand peculiarity. I am guilty as charged. It is indeed possible that she went on to stuff some pages in the kitchen range; or that she had merely kindled a spark with an epigraph, when big boots stamped it out. To begin with, the strategic compromise position is in no way based on the contention that abortion, very much including the hard cases, is morally legitimate.

Its advocates must emphasize that their overall position continues to be that abortion is always wrong because it involves the direct killing of an innocent person. Moreover, they should indicate that they intend to pursue the long-term goal of persuading society that abortion is always wrong, thereby establishing the conditions of a law that fully respects the moral principle of the sanctity of innocent human life. What then is the basis for such a compromise? It is based on the limits of politics and of coercive law.

The fact that something is contrary to the moral law does not automatically mean that it ought to be forbidden by civil law. When a society is deeply divided on a moral issue, it is not always possible or prudent to try to settle the matter fully by the coercive power of law. A large majority of Americans think that as a general rule innocent human life should not be destroyed. There may even be a majority who believe that human life, in some sense, begins at conception.

Publications & Resources

This by itself would seem to provide a sufficient basis for a law generally prohibiting abortion. Unfortunately, however, there are many Americans who believe 1 that the value of unborn human life, important as it is, does not always override other serious values, and 2 that there are different levels of importance to life at various stages of pregnancy. Abortion in the case of a threat to the life of the mother is the best example, since it is possible that one of the very highest prices will be exacted from the mother, father, and the rest of the family for adherence to the moral law.

Rape and incest, serious health problems for the mother those that may inflict substantial and irreparable physical harm , and grave fetal deformities those which, again, are serious and irreparable also constitute extremely difficult circumstances under which to bear a child. It is no answer to such problems, politically speaking, that they occur in only a few cases and therefore are not relevant to the abortion debate. One does not want to exaggerate the difficulties of pregnant women in these situations, as is often done; still, it is desirable to avoid a certain kind of obliviousness to human suffering that adherence to principle can sometimes lead to.


  • ‘What a man this is, with his crowd of women around him!’.
  • Alexia More fun (Anal Alexia Book 2)!
  • Suspect Citizens: Women, Virtue, and Vice in Backlash Politics.
  • Deadlock: A John Hutchinson Novel.
  • The Assassin And The Girl From The Coffee Shop (Girls From The Coffee Shop Book 3)!
  • Download options.

And it is imperative that those who represent the pro-life movement make clear their compassion for those who suffer, even while refusing to concede that sympathy for the suffering can justify the commission of morally evil acts. Equally important must be the denial that abortion, on the whole, alleviates suffering; rather, it must be firmly maintained that abortion deals only with symptoms, serving as an excuse not to deal with the real, underlying causes of suffering.

None of these circumstances changes the basic moral issue, since such considerations do not justify doing a moral evil. This would be true, I would guess, in most times and places. In principle, that heroism is what the ideal law would require with respect to abortion in the hard cases as well. But something short of the ideal may be necessary in the circumstances of a given polity. The pro-life movement can, and ought to, exhort people to respond heroically to difficult moral circumstances.

One way in which many pro-lifers do in fact exhort is by setting an example themselves: But to demand heroism through the criminal law is likely to breed widespread resentment, disrespect for the law, and illegal action both public civil disobedience and surreptitious evasion of the law. It is also likely to lead to a political backlash that results in repeal of the law, that discredits those who supported it, and that makes for legislation far worse than the moderate measure that might have been secured in the first place.

Of course, if not articulated and defended properly, it might come across that way. The greatest virtue of strategic compromise is that it will save many lives that might otherwise have been lost. If a policy of strategic compromise succeeds, it will eliminate a large percentage of our current abortions, numbered these days in the millions.

How many abortions there would be under such a dispensation is hard to say. It would depend partly on the care with which the policy is drafted, so as to prevent exceptions from becoming large loopholes. One presumes that at least some in the medical profession will try to help pregnant women to evade the law. It also will depend on strong pro-life efforts to back effective enforcement efforts.

This justification based on the limits of law would not be readily available for another possible kind of compromise, which I think the pro-life movement ought to avoid, with one unfortunately massive exception. In general, pro-lifers ought to avoid drawing lines on the basis of the stage of pregnancy. The one, unfortunately necessary, exception to avoiding stage-of-pregnancy lines is one at the beginning of pregnancy, i. That factor, plus the deep attachment of American culture to contraception, means that an effort to prohibit abortifacient contraceptives would be hopeless.

It would clearly discredit the pro-life movement with many people. Unfortunately, the battle is likely to shift to that front. Not, by the way, RU But precisely because the future of the pro-life movement is clouded by such things, it becomes all the more important to try to get as strong a principle of respect for life into the law as we can now.

Another element in an effective pro-life strategic compromise would be efforts in the law to support women in carrying their unborn children to term. Especially where the temptation to abort children stems from economic hardship, it is desirable to eliminate this incentive to have an abortion. It is possible for the law to encourage and support pregnant women in their carrying their children to term, whether or not abortions are prohibited.

A very difficult issue in regard to support for pregnant women is whether or not it exacerbates the problem in the long run. Charles Murray and others have made persuasive arguments that government programs in aid of unwed mothers help to create a culture of dependency that worsens the problem by creating perverse incentives. Murray is generally persuasive, although it is not easy to know what conclusions to draw from his analysis. One reason it is very difficult to get Americans to take natural law thought seriously is that historically, i.

Criminal laws that track the moral law closely even where there is little in the mores to support such laws can only serve to exacerbate the suspicion of natural law thinking. An insistence on no exceptions would doom the pro-life movement to political inefficacy for the foreseeable future. The number of Americans who would actively work for a public policy that coincided with the moral law is extremely small. One difficulty here is that a policy of no exceptions would require principled opposition to any and all abortifacient contraceptives.

These activists would presumably have a beneficial effect on the lives of some citizens who were persuaded by their advocacy; and however small the number, such an effect should not be dismissed as minor. But the long-term influence of a pro-life movement that, for the most part, accepted strategic compromise would also be valuable, notwithstanding arguments that it would lose its capacity to persuade or transform by its unwillingness to adhere to principle: He is right when he says that the civil law need not always fully enforce the moral law, and that what the law can do is ultimately a matter of prudential political judgment.

Indeed, must beyond the borders of our gendered moralism. Readers are introduced to Puritan ministers and or her analysis. There is no mention of the and vice.

And the relationship between political inequality racialization of vice, especially sexual licentiousness and and our moral imaginary is thrown into critical relief. Boryczka gestures toward the material foundations attention to irony that a deeply antipapalist religious of our moralism, but leaves this unexamined. For example, movement is the ideological forerunner to Catholic conser- the presentation of Puritan witch-hunting suggests the vatism.

Do Ozzie and Harriet represent real relations, imaginary relations, or, as an both accused of witchcraft, beg for some materialist analysis Althusserian perspective would suggest, a representation pp. Here, and elsewhere, a purely conceptual of our imaginary relation to real material conditions? Other analytic moves, some quite powerful, need a more Finally, it is striking that there is no discussion of careful defense to be truly convincing. For example, in contemporary battles over citizenship.

Political inactivity, by exten- case studies. Here, a seemingly progressive piece of public sion, becomes a moral virtue.